- Escaping The Prison is an amusing escape games game that you can play here, for free. It has been played 5,490,320 times and has received a rating of 9.3 / 10 with 53,860 votes. This exciting adventure game uses Flash to work flawlessly in modern browsers.
- Hector Van Daemon will be executed in 14 days - if he lasts that long in this super-max facility. Wrongly sentenced to death for acts of terrorism, you are his only hope. Can you reform him enough to save him from death row, or even find enough evidence to prove his innocence?
Play Death Row - prison game! Help the prisoner save his life from the electric chair. You have 14 days to make it happen. This inmate has been linked to a bombing of the US government building. He was found guilty of terrorism and sentenced to death. As he maintains his.
Little Big Snake.io
Plumber Duck
Rockoblox 2
Tasty Way
Tactics Core.io
MORT the Sniper 2
Hubris
Sniper Freedom
Warfare 1944
Whizz Words Deluxe
Tetroid
Viking Workout
Earn to Die
Coba
Bubbles
Warfare 1917
Mysteries Truck
Turbo Golf
Sliding Escape
Torture Chamber
Back, You Pointed Spikes! Back!!
Botched Prisoner Executions
Instructions
Arrow keys to move Spacebar to pull levers
Torture Chamber gameplay
Rating:
Teen Caution (more info)
Category:
Related games
Toe Nail Wheel 2
Ragdoll Achievement 2
Super School Day
Sunburn
Twizzed Firefarta
Coco Block
Bee-Do!
Papas Pastaria
Georganism 3
Balls of Life
Moon Waltz
An Ordinary Day
Slay with Santa
Monster Munch
Nightmare Kingdom
Meal or No Meal?
Presidential Candidate or EveryJoe?
Nyan Cat FLY!
Castle Crashing the Beard
Mountain Maniac
Above Average Guy
Goat Mechanic
Madburger 3
Escape The Dungeon
Mahjongg
Into Space 2
Clear Vision II
Greyhound Tycoon
The Last Stand
Day D Tower Rush
Bubble Spinner
Spear Stickman
Age of War
Ball In The Hole
Darwinism 2048
Corporation Inc.
Oiligarchy
Foreign Creature
Pirates of the Stupid Seas
Rotamania
Crush the Castle 2
The Impossible Quiz
Escape: The Car
Battlegrounds
Robo Rush
Escape the Bookstore 2
Sun Stories
Kissmat 2
Free The Prisoner Game
Elegant Wedding
Linkaball
Finding My Heart
Beaver Dive
The Three Prisoners problem appeared in Martin Gardner's 'Mathematical Games' column in Scientific American in 1959.[1][2] It is mathematically equivalent to the Monty Hall problem with car and goat replaced with freedom and execution respectively, and also equivalent to, and presumably based on, Bertrand's box paradox.
- 2Solution
- 3An intuitive explanation
Problem[edit]
Three prisoners, A, B, and C, are in separate cells and sentenced to death. The governor has selected one of them at random to be pardoned. The warden knows which one is pardoned, but is not allowed to tell. Prisoner A begs the warden to let him know the identity of one of the two who are going to be executed. 'If B is to be pardoned, give me C's name. If C is to be pardoned, give me B's name. And if I'm to be pardoned, secretly flip a coin to decide whether to name B or C.'
The warden tells A that B is to be executed. Prisoner A is pleased because he believes that his probability of surviving has gone up from 1/3 to 1/2, as it is now between him and C. Prisoner A secretly tells C the news, who reasons that A's chance of being pardoned is unchanged at 1/3, but he is pleased because his own chance has gone up to 2/3. Which prisoner is correct?
Solution[edit]
The answer is that prisoner A did not gain any information about his own fate, since he already knew that the warden would give him the name of someone else. Prisoner A, prior to hearing from the warden, estimates his chances of being pardoned as 1/3, the same as both B and C. As the warden says B will be executed, it is either because C will be pardoned (1/3 chance), or A will be pardoned (1/3 chance) and the B/C coin the warden flipped came up B (1/2 chance; for a total of a 1/6 chance B was named because A will be pardoned). Hence, after hearing that B will be executed, the estimate of A's chance of being pardoned is half that of C. This means his chances of being pardoned, now knowing B is not, again are 1/3, but C has a 2/3 chance of being pardoned.
Table[edit]
The explanation above may be summarised in the following table. As the warden is asked by A, he can only answer B or C to be executed.
Being pardoned | Warden: 'not B' | Warden: 'not C' | Sum |
---|---|---|---|
A | 1/6 | 1/6 | 1/3 |
B | 0 | 1/3 | 1/3 |
C | 1/3 | 0 | 1/3 |
As the warden has answered that B will not be pardoned, the solution comes from the second column. It appears that the odds for A vs. C to be pardoned are 1:2.
Mathematical formulation[edit]
Call , and the events that the corresponding prisoner will be pardoned, and the event that the warden tells A that prisoner B is to be executed, then, using Bayes' theorem, the posterior probability of A being pardoned, is:
The probability of C being pardoned, on the other hand, is:
The crucial difference making A and C unequal is that but . If A will be pardoned, the warden can tell A that either B or C is to be executed, and hence ; whereas if C will be pardoned, the warden can only tell A that B is executed, so .
An intuitive explanation[edit]
Prisoner A only has a 1/3 chance of pardon. Knowing whether 'B' or 'C' will be executed does not change his chance. After he hears B will be executed, Prisoner A realizes that if he will not get the pardon himself it must only be going to C. That means there is a 2/3 chance for C to get a pardon. This is comparable to the Monty Hall Problem.
Enumeration of possible cases[edit]
The following scenarios may arise:
- A is pardoned and the warden mentions B to be executed: 1/3 × 1/2 = 1/6 of the cases
- A is pardoned and the warden mentions C to be executed: 1/3 × 1/2 = 1/6 of the cases
- B is pardoned and the warden mentions C to be executed: 1/3 of the cases
- C is pardoned and the warden mentions B to be executed: 1/3 of the cases
With the stipulation that the warden will choose randomly, in the 1/3 of the time that A is to be pardoned, there is a 1/2 chance he will say B and 1/2 chance he will say C. This means that taken overall, 1/6 of the time (1/3 [that A is pardoned] × 1/2 [that warden says B]), the warden will say B because A will be pardoned, and 1/6 of the time (1/3 [that A is pardoned] × 1/2 [that warden says C]) he will say C because A is being pardoned. This adds up to the total of 1/3 of the time (1/6 + 1/6) A is being pardoned, which is accurate.
It is now clear that if the warden answers B to A (1/2 of the time of case 1, and case 4), then 1/3 of the time C is pardoned and A will still be executed (case 4), and only 1/6 of the time A is pardoned (case 1). Hence C's chances are (1/3)/(1/2) = 2/3 and A's are (1/6)/(1/2) = 1/3.
The key to this problem is that the warden may not reveal the name of a prisoner who will be pardoned. If we eliminate this requirement, it can demonstrate the original problem in another way. The only change in this example is that prisoner A asks the warden to reveal the fate of one of the other prisoners (not specifying one that will be executed). In this case, the warden flips a coin chooses one of B and C to reveal the fate of. The cases are as follows:
- A pardoned, warden says: B executed (1/6)
- A pardoned, warden says: C executed (1/6)
- B pardoned, warden says: B pardoned (1/6)
- B pardoned, warden says: C executed (1/6)
- C pardoned, warden says: B executed (1/6)
- C pardoned, warden says: C pardoned (1/6)
Each scenario has a 1/6 probability. The original Three Prisoners problem can be seen in this light: The warden in that problem still has these six cases, each with a 1/6 probability of occurring. However, the warden in that case may not reveal the fate of a pardoned prisoner. Therefore, in the 1/6 of the time that case 3 occurs, since saying B is not an option, the warden says C instead (making it the same as case 4). Similarly, in case 6, the warden must say B instead of C (the same as case 5). That leaves cases 4 and 5 with 1/3 probability of occurring and leaves us with the same probability as above.
Why the paradox?[edit]
The tendency of people to provide the answer 1/2 neglects to take into account that the warden may have tossed a coin before he gave his answer. The warden may have answered because is to be released and he tossed a coin. Or, is to be released. But the probabilities of the two events are not equal.
Judea Pearl (1988) used a variant of this example to demonstrate that belief updates must depend not merely on the facts observed but also on the experiment (i.e., query) that led to those facts.[3]
Related problems and applications[edit]
- Principle of restricted choice, an application in the card game bridge
- Prisoner's dilemma, a game theory problem
Notes[edit]
- ^Gardner, Martin (October 1959). 'Mathematical Games: Problems involving questions of probability and ambiguity'. Scientific American. 201 (4): 174–182. doi:10.1038/scientificamerican1059-174.
- ^Gardner, Martin (1959). 'Mathematical Games: How three modern mathematicians disproved a celebrated conjecture of Leonhard Euler'. Scientific American. 201 (5): 188. doi:10.1038/scientificamerican1159-181.
- ^Pearl, J. (1988). Probabilistic Reasoning in Intelligent Systems: Networks of Plausible Inference (First ed.). San Mateo, CA: Morgan Kaufmann.
References[edit]
Latest Prison Executions
- Frederick Mosteller: Fifty Challenging Problems in Probability. Dover 1987 (reprint), ISBN0-486-65355-2, p. 28-29 (restricted online version, p. 28, at Google Books)
- Richard Isaac: Pleasures of Probability. Springer 1995, ISBN978-0-387-94415-9, p. 24-27 (restricted online version, p. 24, at Google Books)